Logic: Difference between revisions

From Rigpa Wiki
Jump to navigation Jump to search
No edit summary
(The double negative has been negated.)
 
(10 intermediate revisions by 4 users not shown)
Line 1: Line 1:
Western philosophy generally identifies two forms of logic: inductive and deductive.
'''Logic''' (Skt. ''nyāya'' or ''yukti''; Tib. རིགས་པ་ or བློ་རིག, ''rikpa'' or ''lo rik'',  [[Wyl.]] ''rigs pa'' or ''blo rig'') employed in Tibetan Buddhist commentaries and debates most commonly takes the form of the Indic syllogism (Skt. ''prayoga''; Tib. སྦྱོར་བ་, ''jorwa'', Wyl. ''sbyor ba'').  


What's important for the Western Dharma student to understand is that, although the form is different, the underlying logic is not—it is the same logic as finds expression in the Aristotelian syllogisms of Western philosophy. This means that any Indic syllogism may be recast as an Aristotelian syllogism, and vice vera.
In order to introduce the formal characteristic of the Indic syllogism, a brief overview of the representations of logic most familiar to people of Western education are presented. It is intended that, by identifying the common elements of Indic and Aristotelian syllogisms, this might aid the reader in gaining insight into the interpretation and application of this powerful system.
We begin by considering the two main branches of logic within Western philosophy, namely: '''inductive''' and '''deductive'''.


==Inductive Logic==
==Inductive Logic==
Line 8: Line 13:
* All known swans are white (specific),  
* All known swans are white (specific),  
* Therefore all swans are white (general).  
* Therefore all swans are white (general).  


The arguments built from inductive reasoning are never very strong, but often very persuasive. If we examine our confidence that today we will not die, we will find that it is supported by a species of inductive logic.
The arguments built from inductive reasoning are never very strong, but often very persuasive. If we examine our confidence that today we will not die, we will find that it is supported by a species of inductive logic.
Line 16: Line 20:


The conclusions of inductive logic reach beyond the support of their arguments, and this is their weakness. But these conclusions are not ''necessarily'' mistaken, and they are not ''unrelated'' to their arguments, and this is their strength. Most thinking proceeds inductively, as the process of induction allows the thinker to make educated guesses that leap beyond the confines of their arguments. However, once a line of reasoning has been discovered via induction, it must be established using deductive analysis for its conclusions to be considered reliable.
The conclusions of inductive logic reach beyond the support of their arguments, and this is their weakness. But these conclusions are not ''necessarily'' mistaken, and they are not ''unrelated'' to their arguments, and this is their strength. Most thinking proceeds inductively, as the process of induction allows the thinker to make educated guesses that leap beyond the confines of their arguments. However, once a line of reasoning has been discovered via induction, it must be established using deductive analysis for its conclusions to be considered reliable.


==Deductive Logic==
==Deductive Logic==
Line 22: Line 25:


===Aristotelian Syllogisms===
===Aristotelian Syllogisms===
The form of deductive logic that would be most familiar to people of Western eduction is that of the Aristotelian syllogism.
The form of deductive logic used in Western philosophy is the Aristotelian syllogism.


For example:
For example:
Line 29: Line 32:
* Therefore, Socrates has a liver.
* Therefore, Socrates has a liver.


Arguments built from deductive logic are very strong. This is because the conclusion is entirely contained within the premises—produced by analytically deducting their common factors. In the above example, 'human being' is the factor common to both of the premises. When it is deducted, and the remainder of the premises combined, you have the conclusion. Thus, if the truth of the premises is accepted, then the truth of the conclusion is irresistible.


Arguements built from deductive logic are very strong. This is because the conclusion is entirely contained within the premises - produced by analytically deducting their common factors. In the above example, 'human being' is the factor common to both of the premises. When it is deducted, and the remainder of the premises combined, you have the conclusion. Thus, if the truth of the premises is accepted, then the truth of the conclusion is irresistable.


{| border="1" style="background:#ffdead;"  
{| border="1" style="background:#ffdead;" cellpadding="4"
| width="100pt" |                                    '''General'''  
| width="100pt" |                                    '''General'''  
| width="120pt" |                                       
| width="120pt" |                                       
Line 51: Line 54:


===Indic Syllogisms===
===Indic Syllogisms===
The form of the syllogism widely used in Tibetan Buddhist literature and debate, is derived from the works of [[Dignāga]] and [[Dharmakīrti]]. [[Dignāga]]'s work was a logical reform based on the system propounded by the Naiyāyikas, which was then later refined by [[Dharmakīrti]].
The form of the syllogism used in Tibetan Buddhism is derived from the works of [[Dignāga]] and [[Dharmakīrti]]. [[Dignāga]]'s work was a reformation of the system propounded by the Naiyāyikas, which was then later refined by [[Dharmakīrti]].


As an example of this form of syllogism, we will take the third of the [[four great logical arguments of the Middle Way]] - taught extensively by the Great Abbot [[Shantarakshita]] in his treatise, the [[Madhyamakalankara]] - the argument of 'neither one nor many'.
As an example of this form of syllogism, we will take the third of the [[four great logical arguments of the Middle Way]]—taught extensively by the Great Abbot [[Shantarakshita]] in his treatise, the [[Madhyamakalankara]]—the argument of 'neither one nor many':


* These things propounded by ourselves and others
:''These things propounded by ourselves and others''<br>
* Do not inherently exist, like a reflection,
:''Do not inherently exist, like a reflection,''<br>
* Because these things lack, in reality, a nature of neither one nor many.
:''Because these things have, in reality, a nature of neither one nor many.''<br>




The process of deductive analysis used here is explained as follows:
The process of deductive analysis used here is explained as follows:


{| border="1" style="background:#ffdead;"  
{| border="1" style="background:#ffdead;" cellpadding="4"
| width="100pt" | '''Subject''' || width="300pt" | These things propounded by ourselves and others
| width="100pt" | '''Subject''' || width="300pt" | These things propounded by ourselves and others
|- style="background:#ffffb1;"  
|- style="background:#ffffb1;"  
| '''Predicate'''  || Do not inherently exist, like a reflection,
| '''Predicate'''  || Do not inherently exist, like a reflection,
|- style="background:#bfffef;"  
|- style="background:#bfffef;"  
| '''Sign''' || Because these things lack, in reality, a nature of neither one nor many.
| '''Sign''' || Because these things have, in reality, a nature of neither one nor many.
|}
|}


Line 74: Line 77:
* The '''predicate''' is the claim that is being made about the subject.  
* The '''predicate''' is the claim that is being made about the subject.  
* The '''sign''' is what is used to establish the '''probandum''' (what is to be proven), which is the valid connection between the '''subject''' and the '''predicate'''.
* The '''sign''' is what is used to establish the '''probandum''' (what is to be proven), which is the valid connection between the '''subject''' and the '''predicate'''.
* The '''probandum''' is the relationship between the subject and the predicate – that which is to be proven through the syllogism
* The '''probandum''' is the relationship between the subject and the predicate—that which is to be proven through the syllogism
 


In assessing the validity of a syllogism, you start with the '''subject''' and work your way through the '''three modes of logic''' until you get to the '''predicate'''.  
In assessing the validity of a syllogism, you start with the '''subject''' and work your way through the '''three modes of logic''' until you get to the '''predicate'''.  
Line 82: Line 84:


Then the '''second''' and '''third modes''' establish the relationship of the '''sign''' to the '''predicate'''. Establishing these three modes establishes the '''probandum'''.
Then the '''second''' and '''third modes''' establish the relationship of the '''sign''' to the '''predicate'''. Establishing these three modes establishes the '''probandum'''.


====The Three Modes of Logic====
====The Three Modes of Logic====
# The first mode is '''The Property of the Subject''' - the sign must be a property of the subject. Here, "lacking, in reality, a nature of neither one nor many" must be a property of "these things propounded by ourselves and others".
# The first mode is '''The Property of the Subject'''—the sign must be a property of the subject. Here, "having, in reality, a nature of neither one nor many" must be a property of "these things propounded by ourselves and others".
# The second mode is '''The Forward Pervasion''' - the sign is completely pervaded by the predicate. This means that all things that are "lacking, in reality, a nature of neither one nor many" "do not inherently exist, like a reflection"
# The second mode is '''The Forward Pervasion'''—the sign is completely pervaded by the predicate. This means that all things that are "having, in reality, a nature of neither one nor many" "do not inherently exist, like a reflection"
# The third mode is '''The Counter Pervasion''' - the negative of the sign is completely pervaded by the negative of the predicate. This means that whatever possesses, in reality, a nature of either one or many must inherently exist.
# The third mode is '''The Counter Pervasion'''—the negative of the predicate is completely pervaded by the negative of the sign. This means that whatever inherently exists must possess, in reality, a nature of either one or many.
 


====Comparision with the Aristotelian Syllogism====
====Comparison with the Aristotelian Syllogism====
The argument of 'neither one nor many' may be expressed in the Aristotelian form:
The argument of 'neither one nor many' may be expressed in the Aristotelian form:
* All things that lack, in reality, a nature of neither one nor many do not inherently exist.
* All things that have, in reality, a nature of neither one nor many do not inherently exist.
* These things propounded by ourselves and others are things that lack, in reality, a nature of neither one nor many.
* These things propounded by ourselves and others are things that have, in reality, a nature of neither one nor many.
* Therefore, these things propounded by ourselves and others do not inherently exist.
* Therefore, these things propounded by ourselves and others do not inherently exist.




{| border="1" style="background:#ffdead;"  
{| border="1" style="background:#ffdead;" cellpadding="4"
| width="100pt" |                                    '''General'''  
| width="100pt" |                                    '''General'''  
| width="250pt" |                                    &nbsp;  
| width="250pt" |                                    &nbsp;  
| width="200pt" style="background:red; color:white" align="center" | All things that lack, in reality, a nature of neither one nor many  
| width="200pt" style="background:red; color:white" align="center" | All things that have, in reality, a nature of neither one nor many  
| width="150pt" |                                    do not inherently exist, like a reflection
| width="150pt" |                                    do not inherently exist, like a reflection
|-  
|-  
|                                                    '''Specific'''  
|                                                    '''Specific'''  
| align="right" |                                    These things propounded by ourselves and others are
| align="right" |                                    These things propounded by ourselves and others are
| style="background:red; color:white" align="center"| things that lack, in reality, a nature of neither one nor many
| style="background:red; color:white" align="center"| things that have, in reality, a nature of neither one nor many
|                                                    &nbsp;
|                                                    &nbsp;
|-  
|-  
Line 115: Line 115:




The statement of the '''general''' premise of an Aristotelian syllogism corresponds to both the '''second''' and '''third logical modes'''. The term "all" (which makes it a general statement) covers both the foward and counter pervasions, establishing the relationship between the '''predicate''' and the '''sign'''.
The statement of the '''general''' premise of an Aristotelian syllogism corresponds to both the '''second''' and '''third logical modes'''. The term "all" (which makes it a general statement) covers both the forward and counter pervasions, establishing the relationship between the '''predicate''' and the '''sign'''.


The '''specific''' instance premise covers the '''first logical mode''', establishing that the '''sign''' is a property of the '''subject'''.
The '''specific''' instance premise covers the '''first logical mode''', establishing that the '''sign''' is a property of the '''subject'''.
Line 121: Line 121:
What is analytically deducted from the Aristotelian syllogism corresponds to the '''sign'''.
What is analytically deducted from the Aristotelian syllogism corresponds to the '''sign'''.


The Aristotelian '''conclusion''' corresponds to the Indic '''probandum''' - that which is to be proven.
The Aristotelian '''conclusion''' corresponds to the Indic '''probandum'''—that which is to be proven.
 
 
[[Category:Pramana]]

Latest revision as of 18:16, 16 July 2018

Logic (Skt. nyāya or yukti; Tib. རིགས་པ་ or བློ་རིག, rikpa or lo rik, Wyl. rigs pa or blo rig) employed in Tibetan Buddhist commentaries and debates most commonly takes the form of the Indic syllogism (Skt. prayoga; Tib. སྦྱོར་བ་, jorwa, Wyl. sbyor ba).

What's important for the Western Dharma student to understand is that, although the form is different, the underlying logic is not—it is the same logic as finds expression in the Aristotelian syllogisms of Western philosophy. This means that any Indic syllogism may be recast as an Aristotelian syllogism, and vice vera.

In order to introduce the formal characteristic of the Indic syllogism, a brief overview of the representations of logic most familiar to people of Western education are presented. It is intended that, by identifying the common elements of Indic and Aristotelian syllogisms, this might aid the reader in gaining insight into the interpretation and application of this powerful system.

We begin by considering the two main branches of logic within Western philosophy, namely: inductive and deductive.

Inductive Logic

Inductive logic is reasoning from the specific to the general.

For example:

  • All known swans are white (specific),
  • Therefore all swans are white (general).

The arguments built from inductive reasoning are never very strong, but often very persuasive. If we examine our confidence that today we will not die, we will find that it is supported by a species of inductive logic.

  • All known days have passed without my death (specific),
  • Therefore [on any given day] I will not die (general).

Of course, we understand that one day we will die, but it's the rigour that inductive logic lacks that allows us to not be very compelled by this fact.

The conclusions of inductive logic reach beyond the support of their arguments, and this is their weakness. But these conclusions are not necessarily mistaken, and they are not unrelated to their arguments, and this is their strength. Most thinking proceeds inductively, as the process of induction allows the thinker to make educated guesses that leap beyond the confines of their arguments. However, once a line of reasoning has been discovered via induction, it must be established using deductive analysis for its conclusions to be considered reliable.

Deductive Logic

Deductive logic is reasoning from the general to the specific.

Aristotelian Syllogisms

The form of deductive logic used in Western philosophy is the Aristotelian syllogism.

For example:

  • All human beings have a liver.
  • Socrates is a human being.
  • Therefore, Socrates has a liver.

Arguments built from deductive logic are very strong. This is because the conclusion is entirely contained within the premises—produced by analytically deducting their common factors. In the above example, 'human being' is the factor common to both of the premises. When it is deducted, and the remainder of the premises combined, you have the conclusion. Thus, if the truth of the premises is accepted, then the truth of the conclusion is irresistible.


General   All human beings have a liver
Specific Socrates is a human being  
Conclusion Therefore, Socrates   has a liver.


Indic Syllogisms

The form of the syllogism used in Tibetan Buddhism is derived from the works of Dignāga and Dharmakīrti. Dignāga's work was a reformation of the system propounded by the Naiyāyikas, which was then later refined by Dharmakīrti.

As an example of this form of syllogism, we will take the third of the four great logical arguments of the Middle Way—taught extensively by the Great Abbot Shantarakshita in his treatise, the Madhyamakalankara—the argument of 'neither one nor many':

These things propounded by ourselves and others
Do not inherently exist, like a reflection,
Because these things have, in reality, a nature of neither one nor many.


The process of deductive analysis used here is explained as follows:

Subject These things propounded by ourselves and others
Predicate Do not inherently exist, like a reflection,
Sign Because these things have, in reality, a nature of neither one nor many.


  • The subject is that which is under investigation, about which a claim is being made.
  • The predicate is the claim that is being made about the subject.
  • The sign is what is used to establish the probandum (what is to be proven), which is the valid connection between the subject and the predicate.
  • The probandum is the relationship between the subject and the predicate—that which is to be proven through the syllogism

In assessing the validity of a syllogism, you start with the subject and work your way through the three modes of logic until you get to the predicate.

The first mode establishes the relationship of the subject with the sign.

Then the second and third modes establish the relationship of the sign to the predicate. Establishing these three modes establishes the probandum.

The Three Modes of Logic

  1. The first mode is The Property of the Subject—the sign must be a property of the subject. Here, "having, in reality, a nature of neither one nor many" must be a property of "these things propounded by ourselves and others".
  2. The second mode is The Forward Pervasion—the sign is completely pervaded by the predicate. This means that all things that are "having, in reality, a nature of neither one nor many" "do not inherently exist, like a reflection"
  3. The third mode is The Counter Pervasion—the negative of the predicate is completely pervaded by the negative of the sign. This means that whatever inherently exists must possess, in reality, a nature of either one or many.

Comparison with the Aristotelian Syllogism

The argument of 'neither one nor many' may be expressed in the Aristotelian form:

  • All things that have, in reality, a nature of neither one nor many do not inherently exist.
  • These things propounded by ourselves and others are things that have, in reality, a nature of neither one nor many.
  • Therefore, these things propounded by ourselves and others do not inherently exist.


General   All things that have, in reality, a nature of neither one nor many do not inherently exist, like a reflection
Specific These things propounded by ourselves and others are things that have, in reality, a nature of neither one nor many  
Conclusion Therefore, these things propounded by ourselves and others   do not inherently exist, like a reflection.


The statement of the general premise of an Aristotelian syllogism corresponds to both the second and third logical modes. The term "all" (which makes it a general statement) covers both the forward and counter pervasions, establishing the relationship between the predicate and the sign.

The specific instance premise covers the first logical mode, establishing that the sign is a property of the subject.

What is analytically deducted from the Aristotelian syllogism corresponds to the sign.

The Aristotelian conclusion corresponds to the Indic probandum—that which is to be proven.